Cicero Denounces Catiline [detail] fresco by Cesare Maccari |
Introduction
Two
of the most influential political theorists in human history were
Aristotle and Thomas Hobbes, each being the father of a political
school(s) of thought that shaped mankind thereafter. Though separated
by centuries, Aristotle and Hobbes are separated more profoundly in
their respective doctrines. Their differences are on the level of the
fundamental to such an extent that one can claim that they stand on
opposite ends of a spectrum, particularly in their philosophy of man
and the ends for which man exists and acts. For Aristotle, man is
naturally a social and, therefore, political animal ‒man is ordered
toward the community. For Hobbes, man is anything but ‒man
is naturally ordered toward the the individual, and that individual
is himself.
But
which one is right? Is Aristotle the the disconnected idealist and
Hobbes the one grounded in observational reality; or, is Aristotle
seeing past the evident corruption to the true nature of men and
society, and Hobbes just steeped too much in the puritanical tea of
the age in which he wrote? Well, we observe men voluntarily acting
for a common good; we also observe men behaving selfishly. If forced
to choose between these two philosophers, Aristotle is to be
preferred ‒man
is
a social animal, for though Hobbes makes certain real and accurate
observations on the behavior and nature of man, the latter, due to
his fundamental epistemological and metaphysical denials, fails to
see the inherent goodness of human nature and the good to which it is
naturally ordered. As a result of these fundamental errors, Hobbes
stitches together his own monstrosity of a political doctrine in his
Leviathan
in which, if accurate, man's life would truly be "solitary,
poor, nasty, brutish, and short."1
Let us first examine Aristotle's views in summary, then Hobbes', and
finally engage in the comparative analysis.
Aristotle |
Aristotle:
man as social/political animal in the
Politics.
Hence it is evident
that a city is a natural production, and that man is naturally a
political [social]
animal.
‒Aristotle, Politics,
1253a3.
Aristotle's
entire political treatise is built upon his his ethical,
anthropological, and natural philosophy. In short: nature acts for an
end; that end is the good and it is common, i.e. not diminished for
others when had; the common good is predicated of the individual good
to such an extent that the individual good is intrinsically tied to
the good of the community; and the end of man can only be achieved by
virtuous and lawful behavior. Thus the
Politics entirely depends upon the idea that man is a
social animal, and Aristotle devotes the first considerations of his
treatise to this point.
He
builds up to this fundamental concept by presenting to us a layered
hierarchy of human and natural associations or societies, one
connected to another and subordinated by nature to the whole in a
similar way that the various parts of the body form and are
subordinated to the good of the whole body.2
From lowest to highest, the natural associations are: 1.) personal
associations (as St. Thomas summarizes it3),
2.) households or families, 3.) villages (or neighborhoods), and,
finally, 4.) the state/city itself which is the political/social
(societal) community.
Aristotle
clearly points to the observable fact that individuals cannot exist
without others to help them fulfill their own, individual, and most
fundamental ends. This insufficiency is the cause of the first
natural association: that between man and woman. From there, new and
higher associations are naturally produced to fulfill the hierarchy
of ends for man ‒the lowest being fundamental existence to the
highest which is happiness, for "living well" presupposes
that one's basic needs are first fulfilled. The "personal
association" of man and woman produces the "household"
or "family" so as to fulfill the daily needs of basic
subsistence and existence. The households grow and multiply over time
to produce the next natural association: the "village",
where the non-daily needs of man are fulfilled, and where households
first encounter the production of other households which contribute
to ends higher than fundamental existence. As households naturally
grow and multiply, so too the villages. This leads Aristotle to the
culminating point of his argument that the state is a natural
association:
And when many villages
so entirely join themselves together as in every respect to form but
one society, that society is a city, and contains in itself, if I may
so speak, the end and perfection of government: first founded that we
might live, but continued that we may live happily. For which reason
every city must be allowed to be the work of nature, if we admit that
the original society between male and female is; for to this as their
end all subordinate societies tend, and the end of everything is the
nature of it. For what every being is in its most perfect state, that
certainly is the nature of that being, whether it be a man, a horse,
or a house: besides, whatsoever produces the final cause and the end
which we desire, must be best; but a government complete in itself is
that final cause and what is best.
‒Aristotle, Politics,
1252b28-1253a2.
When
villages begin to associate, this produces Aristotle's state/city
(polis),
which, due to the combined efforts of the many villages and
households, all the natural ends of man are fulfilled (i.e.
self-sufficieny or sustainability is achieved) to achieve his
ultimate end: happiness. Furthermore, as each association naturally
has its ruler, so too does the state, for the ruler imposes law and
thus maintains an orderly framework where those within the
association can live with (relative) tranquility to achieve the ends
proper to the association governed. Thus, each association differs
not only in degree but in kind, as each has a different proximate
end. But the proximate end of the state is also the final end of men.
Therefore, all men are ordered toward the political community by
their nature as it (the state) is that which best achieves the
natural, final end of man.4
To
summarize Aristotle's argument, as nature (essence) is the end ‒the
that-for-the-sake-of-which a thing comes to be‒
and as man is insufficient of his individual self to accomplish the
perfection of his nature, his nature can only be completed or best
accomplished in an association that has self-sufficiency or complete
sustainability as its end. That final association is the city or
state, that to which, then, man naturally tends from his first
personal association. And that which produces the final cause (on the
natural level) is supreme. To put it another way, that which is most
proximate to the final cause is highest. Since nature acts for an
end, man is by nature a political (social) animal.5
As
a corollary to this, Aristotle points out that if a man is not
politically/socially inclined, he must be either sub-human or
quasi-divine. Leaving the quasi-divine idea aside, a non/anti-social
man must be quarrelsome and solitary, i.e, if he is not
political/social by nature, then his "nature" is "solitary,
poor, nasty, brutish, and [will probably be] short." His
warlike, solitary nature is "unnatural" (so to speak), not
inclined to human nature's proper end, for nature does nothing
vainly; and man, above all other animals, has the power of reason as
is evidenced in his power of speech by which he communicates his
ideas to achieve his ends. Thus, by virtue of reason, Aristotle
asserts that man is the most
political/social of all animals, for it is only the reason that can
comprehend the end and direct one or many towards it.6
And
the end or good of man is "happiness/the good life/living well"
which consists of:
...an activity of the
soul according to virtue, and, if the virtues are many, then
according to the best and most complete virtue....What should prevent
us, then from saying that a man is happy when he acts in accordance
with complete virtue and is sufficiently furnished with external
goods?
‒Aristotle. Nicomachean
Ethics, 1098a17, 1101a15.
Thomas Hobbes |
Thomas
Hobbes: man not as social animal in the
Leviathan.
The final cause, end,
or design of men, who naturally love liberty, and dominion over
others, in the introduction of that restraint upon themselves, in
which we see them live in commonwealths [the
state], is the foresight of their own preservation, and of
a more contented life thereby; that is to say, of getting themselves
out of that miserable condition of war, which is necessarily
consequent...to the natural passions of men, when there is no visible
power to keep them in awe, and tie them by fear of punishment to the
performance of their covenants, and observation of those laws of
nature.
‒Thomas Hobbes,
Leviathan, chapter 17.
Hobbes
political philosophy is the antithesis to Aristotle's teachings. In
fact, Hobbes devotes the entire 17th chapter of the Leviathan
to point-by-point arguments explicitly against Aristotle's writings
addressed above. Yet this chapter is also a summarization of his
treatment of man which leads him to this alternate consideration of
the commonwealth/state ‒man, for Hobbes, is not a social
animal, and, as a consequence, the political community is not
natural. Let us examine the principal points which led him to these
assertions.
Hobbes
axiomatically reworks (rejects) classical (and scholastic) philosophy
by positing empiricist, mechanistic, and nominalist principles from
which to work: e.g. imagination is nothing other than decaying
sense7;
science is merely the knowable consequence of sensed and remembered
antecedent facts8;
thoughts are regulated by desire9;
the will is nothing other than the last appetite prior to action10;
truth is really the proper ordering of nomenclature11;
understanding is nothing but a conception in the mind caused by
speech12;
reasoning is nothing other than a mathematical exercise of addition
and subtraction13;
to think one can speak of immaterial realities is absurdity14;
we can have no real or useful natural knowledge of God15;
all men are equal, not just insofar as they have the same nature, but
in the powers of the mind and body16;
etc.
These
premises serve as the backdrop and foundation to Hobbes political
doctrines. We cannot really know the immaterial causes of things, our
naming of them being absurdities. Nor can we trace back from effect
to cause and have a real or meaningful knowledge of God or His
existence. As a consequence, though there may be a natural law, man
can have no meaningful understanding of it in such wise as to base
his morality in it. Man desires the good, but not because they are
good in themselves, but because it is desirable, it is called
"good". That which is detested is called "evil".
We know from our senses about sensible (or at least
quantifiable) things; and, our desire drives the reasoning process, a
mere exercise in computation, in achieving what one desires ‒the
sensible "good"‒ or avoiding what one dislikes ‒the
sensible "evil".
Then
what makes us moral? Nothing. The State of Nature17
is that of every man for himself ‒the
antithesis of the concept of man as social animal. For "men have
no pleasure, but on the contrary a great deal of grief, in keeping
company, where there is no power able to over-awe them all."18
This warlike state is due to men's equality and his Rights of Nature19
which gives him absolute liberty to do what he will for his own
preservation, even "to one another's body".20
And so, if there is nothing to inhibit a man in the state of nature
to do whatever he wills to procure his own desired ends, nothing is
"unjust". Thus, from our first societies/associations
listed by Aristotle to the last, none have society of any level as an
end, but strictly
as a means to one's individual, personal end. Each man exists by
nature for himself. Therefore, none of the associations/societies are
natural. Man is not naturally a social/political animal.
The
state, or commonwealth, is a contrivance of man where he, with
other men, in order to escape the state of nature where men live in
perpetual fear for their life, surrender their natural rights to the
state and its sovereign. Therefore, those natural rights leave the
individual men and are transferred completely to the sovereign of the
commonwealth. Then what he desires is "good", what
he detests is "evil", and no one can say otherwise
for their rights have become forfeit. It is only in the commonwealth
that those "laws of nature" come to be and are enforced.
For the laws of
nature, as justice, equity, modesty, mercy, and, in sum, doing to
others, as we would be done to, of themselves, without the terror of
some power, to cause them to be observed, are contrary
to our natural passions, that carry us to partiality, pride, revenge,
and the like. [emphasis added]
‒Thomas Hobbes.
Leviathan, chapter 17.
Thus
rights precede law. And virtue, Aristotle's "good life", is
not an end or the good of man, but is contrary to his nature.
Crucifixion from Weingarten Missal, c. 1210 |
Analysis:
Who is right?
Where
does one begin in the comparative analysis with these two who are
apparent polar opposites? Their doctrines are diametrically opposed
at the level of principle. Aristotle holds that man is by nature a
social animal, and that (political) society exists for the sake of
the common good of man: happiness, which is the virtuous life. Hobbes
holds than man is a social animal by artifice, that he is naturally
an individualistic and antisocial animal, and that political society
exists to keep men from killing each other. For Hobbes, the "good"
is relative to the individual who calls it so, and virtue is
unnatural. It has been noted:
Ethical relativism
cannot possibly be the basis for a good democracy because it is
inherently incapable of providing a blueprint for unity or an
inspiration for decency. Nor can it provide a basis for either
tolerance or mutual respect.21
One
can assert this not just for democracy but for all forms of
government. The Christian man can certainly see this. But Hobbes was
a Christian and Aristotle a pagan, yet the above quotation would far
more resonate with our classical philosopher than our "Christian"
legal positivist. What can account for this? Can there be a
reconciliation?
As
stated above, Aristotle and Hobbes disagree on the level of
principle. For two or more people to have a rational dialogue, they
must find some common ground from which to commence. If they
cannot agree on anything, then no dialogue can ensue ‒they will end
up talking past each other. Where is the common ground with our two
philosophers?
Aristotle
thinks we can have some real knowledge of immaterial realities; not
so for Hobbes. Aristotle holds that natures and ends are
proportionate and commensurate with each other; for Hobbes, natures
and ends are opposed (at least the natures and ends that Aristotle
propose are opposed, according to Hobbes). Aristotle thinks man can
work for virtue and the state helps
him achieve this; Hobbes thinks man works for himself and the state
imposes
"virtue" on his contrarian nature. Aristotle recognizes
that man can, and often is, vicious, but nature is still good, for
man's proper end remains22;
Hobbes effectively asserts that man's fallen or wounded nature is not
fallen or wounded, but is
nature (this, of course, opens up many theological problems, not the
least of which is our necessity of the Incarnation, Passion &
Death, Resurrection, and Ascension of Our Lord) . Aristotle has been
called the realist,
and in his works we see that he always proceeds from the more known
(the sensible order) to the less known (that which is metaphysica).
Hobbes has been called an empiricist,
and that we proceed from the senses, but we never really (nor can we
with any real meaning) intellectually go beyond the sensible order.
Perhaps this is a common ground: sensible experience; for both
Aristotle and Hobbes would agree that it is at this level we must
begin our rational investigations. But experience can also be a
difficult place to start.
It
is difficult to argue with a man's experiences. There is no altruism
for Hobbes. Why? Perhaps he never experienced it; perhaps he never
practiced it himself. A brief look into his biography might allow for
this possibility. If a man puts on a coat, he does so to get or keep
warm. If he takes off his coat and puts it around his daughter's
shoulders, he does so that she may be warm, though he might suffer a
little. Hobbes would look for a selfish motive in this. But any
decent father would say that he did this strictly for the good of the
daughter, at the sacrifice of his own good, not for praise or fear of
punishment. Most fathers would call this a simple act of love: an act
where the good of another is sought. But if Hobbes never
experienced anything like this himself, his conclusions, then, should
not be too surprising. However, if Hobbes ever did experience
anything like this, his whole edifice instantly becomes a house of
cards. His modernity, then, becomes contrived and forced, and he thus
violates his own principles of starting from sensible experience.
Which is it? We cannot see into his soul to know.
But
there are experiences that all men can work from. Firstly, all
men want to be happy. Men certainly do disagree in what
happiness consists, but that is a disagreement on the particulars; a
general conception of happiness remains. But it is observable that we
do not act for the sake of mere survival. Secondly, Aristotle's
observations still holds true: individual men are insufficient in
themselves. Man does not regenerate from division like
earthworms, he requires a partner of the opposite sex to propagate
the species ‒this is indisputable fact. He does not need arguments
to see this; this is on the level of the self evident (in spite of
the non-arguments of today's generation). And it is observed that to
achieve the first point, man regularly seeks to alleviate the second.
Again, he does not need rational prompting to see this, he does so,
dare we say, by nature. Thus, when people get married and bind
themselves to this fundamental society, they have happiness as a
goal. If this is granted, Aristotle's arguments must then be
conceded. Man, logically then, must go out of himself to
achieve happiness; he must must be societal in order to
be happy. When he fails to do so, he is miserable (and in this
selfish, post-Hobbesian age, that failure in social behavior explains
the terribly high divorce and abortion rates). The Hobbesian order
does not allow for happiness, it merely exchanges one misery for
another. The one addition a Christian man would want to make to the
Aristotelian doctrine is that man's ultimate happiness lies in
beatitude which is in part achieved by the virtuous life. But
beatitude is a supernatural end. Nonetheless, even in beatitude there
is society, the society of the creature in the presence of the
Creator in Whose image he was made. Man's happiness, the perfection
of his nature, then, is not only achieved through society, it
is Society.
Finis.
ENDNOTES
1Thomas
Hobbes. Leviathan, part 1, chapter 13, page 100.
2Aristotle.
Politics, 1253a, 20-25.
3St.
Thomas Aquinas. Commentary on Aristotle's Politics, chapter
1, commentary at 6, page 9.
4Aristotle.
Politics, 1252a25-1253a3.
5ibid.
1252b 28-1253a 3.
6ibid.
1253a, 3-20.
7Thomas
Hobbes. Leviathan, part 1, chapter 2, page 23.
8ibid.
chapter 9, page 69.
9ibid.
chapter 3, page 29.
10ibid.
chapter 6, page 54.
11ibid.
chapter 4, page 37.
12ibid.
page 39.
13ibid.
chapter 5, page 41.
14ibid.
page 43.
15ibid.
chapter 11, page 85.
16ibid.
chapter 13, page 98.
17cf.
the entire 13th chapter of Leviathan.
18Thomas
Hobbes. Leviathan, chapter 13, page 99.
19cf.
the entire 14th chapter of Leviathan.
20Thomas
Hobbes. Leviathan, chapter 14, page 103.
21Dr.
Donald DeMarco. From an article contained in the syllabus for the
Political Philosophy class for Holy Apostles College and Seminary
(HACS PHL712: Political Philosophy Fall 2011).
22Aristotle
has some level of recognition of the fallen or wounded nature of man
as expressed in the Christian tradition. In spite of this, and
though man is often vicious, his nature is still ordered to the end
which is good. Even when performing vicious acts, men do not seek
evil qua evil, but they seek it due to a misappropriated or
lesser good perceived.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aquinas,
St. Thomas. Commentary on Aristotle's Politics, Richard Regan
(translator), Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company,
2007.
Aristotle.
Nicomachean Ethics, Hippocrates Apostle (translator),
Grinnell, Iowa: The Peripatetic Press, 1984.
______.
Politics, Hippocrates Apostle (translator), Grinnell, Iowa:
The Peripatetic Press, 1986.
______.
Politics: A Treatise on Government, William Ellis
(translator), Project Gutenberg, June 5, 2009 [EBook #6762].
November 1, 2011
<http://www.gutenberg.org/files/6762/6762-h/6762-h.htm>.
Hobbes,
Thomas. The English Works of Thomas Hobbes ‒ The
Elements of Philosophy: Concerning Body, Sir William Molesworth
(ed.), London: John Bohn, 1839. Internet Archive, April 1, 2008.
November 2, 2011
<http://www.archive.org/stream/englishworkstho21hobbgoog#page/n36/mode/2up>.
______.
Leviathan, Michael Oakeshott (editor), New York: Collier
Books, 1962.
______.
Leviathan, Edward White and
David Widger (production), Project Gutenberg, October
11, 2009 [EBook #3207]. November 2, 2011
<http://www.gutenberg.org/files/3207/3207-h/3207-h.htm#2HCH0017>.
DeMarco,
Donald, Ph.D. "Syllabus for HACS PHL712: Political Philosophy
Fall 2011", November 3, 2011
<http://fishersnet.blackboard.com/bbcswebdav/pid-486319-dt-content-rid-25669_1/courses/HACS_D_PHL712_Fall_2011/Political_Philosophy_Syllabus2.pdf>.